06 Limits of the form
Sections 2.2 and 2.3 cover the idea of limit of a function at a point, using
the so-called "epsilon-delta" definition of limit, which is named after
the Greek letters that are used by convention in the definition. (But it's
important to remember that when the definition is applied, the corresponding
quantities are not always named epsilon and delta.) You might have
already seen this definition. In this course, we are less interested in
using the definition to prove that a given limit has a certain value and
more interested in giving rigorous proofs of theorems about limits.
Here, as is usually true in our textbook, "function" means "real-valued
function of a single real variable."
Definition: Let be
a function. Let and be real numbers. We say that
if for every , there is a
such that if is a real number satisfying ,
then is defined at and . The notation
is read "the limit of as approaches is equal to ."
(My definition here leaves out the condition in the book's definition
that be defined on some open interval containing except possibly at
itself. Instead, it says that is defined for all satisfying
, which is the same thing.)
Let's apply this definition to prove that
I want to explore in some detail how one might think about this problem.
Here, , , and
The function is defined everywhere, so the condition that the
function is defined is satisfied everywhere.
(Proofs will sometimes not explicitly mention checking this condition, if
it seems obvious, but it is an important part of the definition.)
We must begin with an arbitrary positive number We must find
some positive number that satisfies: for any , if ,
then Note that our proof has to work for any We have picked
some specific but arbitrary to work with. We don't know anything about
it except that it is greater than zero. We have to produce a specific that
will work for that specific , but because is arbitrary, our value
for will depend on the specific that we are given. This is a
roundabout way of saying that we actually want to define as
a function of
So, our goal is to force the quantity to be small, and we have to do
that by making small. We need to figure out what might
have to do with . Hopefully, we notice that
We can make as small as we like, but what to do about the ?
Notice that we don't have to make small, since we can make as small
as we like. We just have to make sure that is not too big. That is,
we want to bound . In fact, since we are going to make close to 3,
it should follow that is close to . Specifically, if we make sure
that , then and . In particular,
as long as , we will have . Then to make the product
be less than we only have to make .
That is, as long as is less than 1 and also less than ,
we will have .
So, if we choose our to be the function of given by
, then will imply
which is just what we needed to show. Let's put this into a formal proof—which should
not include any of the exploratory thinking that we have just worked through:
Proof that
Let . We want to find such that for any , if ,
then . Define
Suppose satisfies . Since , we have
and , and it follows that Therefore,
as we wanted to show.
Let's apply similar reasoning to the proof of the sum and product rules for limits:
If and ,
then
and
The two limits that we are given in the hypothesis mean that we can force
and to be as small as we like by making small enough (but
non-zero, since knowing the two limits does not tell us anything about what happens
to and when is exactly equal to .)
For the limit of the sum we need to force ,
using our control over and . Here, we should notice that
and the triangle inequality allows us to relate this back to and
Since we can force both and to be small by choosing small
enough, we are good! But we need to do it formally. Given any , we can force
by making for some .
And we can force by making for some .
We can force both conditions by making
So, we choose Then for any satisfying
, we have
For the product ,we need to force to be small. The proof
is probably not something that you would come up with quickly on your own, but it
uses the same general ideas that we have been discussing.
Again, we want to relate the quantity back to and
Note that if we had we could factor out the to
get , and we see the that we are looking for. There is no
in , but we can use the trick of adding and subtracting
the same quantity to introduce into the formula, and things work out
nicely using the triangle inequality:
We can force and to be as small as we like.
As long as we can also put some limit on , the quantity as
a whole will be small. But as , which means
that if is close to , then will not be too much
bigger than .
So, given , using the fact that ,
choose , such that
implies , which in turn implies
(The last inequality follows from the last theorem
in the fourth reading guide.) Choose such that
implies And choose
such that implies .
(The denominator uses rather than to avoid the problem of division by zero
in the case where is zero.) Finally, let .
Then, for any that satisfies , we have
Note that the strange denominators in and were
chosen so that we could end up with at the end of the preceding calculation. Of course, I had
to look ahead to see what was needed to make that happen.
After all that, you should probably carefully reread the proofs from the textbook and make sure that you understand
how the proofs of the limit theorems work.
Occasionally, you might need to prove that a limit does not exist. That is,
for some function and some , is not
for any number . The definition of can
be expressed symbolically as
The negation of this statement is which is expressed as
To say that does not exist is to say ,
This adds another quantifier to the previous statement. So, does not exist if and only if
This statement is quite complicated logically, and it is not surprising that it can be difficult to keep
things straight when proving that a limit does not exist.
However, the basic idea is that if there are points, arbitrarily close
to for which the value of is bounded away from by some positive distance, For a simple
example, because there are values of arbitrarily close to 1 such that
the distance of from 3 is greater than 1. (In fact, of course, in this case, for all
close to 1, the distance is greater than 1 — which is a stronger condition that
we need.)
So, let's show that Now, for
, so there are
points arbitrarily close to 0 for which is very close (in fact equal to) 0.
However, if we look at the points
we have So we also get points arbitrarily close to 0 for which
is bounded away from 0. In particular, letting , we see that for any , we can
find a point such that and (namely, choose an odd natural number so that
, and let ). Convince yourself that this is exactly what we need to
satisfy the definition given above for
Of course, to show that does not exist, we need to
show that for any number ,
Here is a more formal proof of that fact:
Let be any number. Let We want to show that for any , there is
a number such that but
Let be any positive number. In the case , let be an odd natural number such that
, which exists by the Archimedian property of
and let . Then and
. Since and ,
we see that as we wanted to show.
In the case , let be an odd natural number such that
,
and let . Then and
. Since and ,
we see that so that we are done in this case as well.
(back to contents)